WELCOME TO YOUR BLOG...!!!.YOU ARE N°

When Words Fail



by Frank Wilczek
Nobel Laureate in Physics 2004
Herman Feshbach professor of physics at MIT

Scientists have to struggle
with words that don't fit reality
_______________________________________

Language is a social creation. 

It encodes the common experience 
of many people, past and present, 
and has been sculpted mainly 
to communicate our everyday needs. 

Ordinary language 
is most certainly not a product 
of the critical investigation of concepts. 

Yet scientists 
learn, think and communicate in it 
during much of their lives. 

Ordinary language is therefore
an unavoidable scientific tool 
— rich and powerful, 
but also quite imperfect.

One scientific imperfection of language,
perhaps the most obvious, is its incompleteness.

For example, there are no 
common words for several 
of the most central concepts
of quantum theory, 
such as the linearity of state-space 
and the use of tensor products 
to describe composite systems. 

To be sure, we’ve developed 
some applicable jargon 
— ‘superposition’ and ‘entanglement’, 
respectively, are the words we use — 
but the words are unusual ones, 
not likely to convey much to outsiders,
and their literal meaning is misleading to boot.

Although it creates cultural barriers 
and contributes to the balkanization of knowledge,
such enrichment and slight abuse of language 
is not conceptually problematic.

Much more insidious, 
and more fundamentally interesting, 
is the opposite case: 
when ordinary language is too complete. 

When something has a name, 
and is commonly employed in discourse, 
it is seductive to assume 
that it refers to a coherent concept,
and an element of reality. 

But it need not.

And the more pervasive the word, 
the more difficult it can be to evade its spell.

Few words are more pervasive than ‘now’.

According to his own account, 
the greatest difficulty Einstein 
encountered in reaching
the special theory of relativity 
was the necessity to break free 
from the idea that there is 
an objective, universal ‘now’: 

“[A]ll attempts to clarify 
this paradox satisfactorily 
were condemned to failure 
as long as the axiom 
of the absolute character of times, 
viz., of simultaneity, unrecognizedly 
was anchored in the unconscious. 
Clearly to recognize this axiom
and its arbitrary character really implies
already the solution of the problem.”

[Einstein, A. “Autobiographical notes” in Albert Einstein,
Philosopher-Scientist (ed. Schilpp, P.) (Library of Living
Philosophers, 1949).]

Einstein’s original 1905 paper 
begins with a lengthy discussion, 
practically free of equations,
of the physical operations involved 
in synchronizing clocks at distant points. 

He then shows that these same operations,
implemented by a moving system of observers, 
leads to differing determinations
of which events occur “at the same time”.

As relativity undermines ‘now’, 
quantum theory undermines ‘here’. 

Heisenberg had Einstein’s analysis 
specifically in mind when,
in the opening of his seminal paper 
on the new quantum mechanics in 1925, 
he advocated the formulation of physical laws 
using observable quantities only. 

But while classical theory 
has a naïve conception 
of a particle’s position, 
described by a single coordinate 
(a triple of numbers, 
for three-dimensional space), 
quantum theory requires 
this to be replaced 
by a much more abstract quantity.

One aspect of the situation is that 
if you don’t measure the position, 
you must not assume
that it has a definite value. 

Many successful calculations 
of physical processes 
using quantum mechanics 
are based on performing
a precise form of averaging 
over many different positions 
where a particle ‘might be found’. 

These calculations would be ruined 
if you assumed that the particle 
was always at some definite place. 

You can choose to measure its position, 
but performing such a measurement
involves disturbing the particle. 

It changes both the question and the answer.

Einstein himself 
was never reconciled 
to the loss of ‘here’. 

In his greatest achievement,
the general theory of relativity, 
Einstein relied heavily 
on the primitive notions of events 
in space–time and (proper) distance 
between nearby events. 

These notions rely on unambiguous
association of times and places 
— ‘nows’ and ‘heres’ — 
to individual objects of reality 
(though not, of course, 
on the existence of a universal ‘now’). 

Understandably impressed 
by the success of his theory,
Einstein was loath to sacrifice its premises. 

He resisted modern quantum theory, 
and did not participate in its sweeping success 
in elucidating problem after great problem.

Ironically, the sacrifice he feared 
has not (yet) proved necessary. 

On the contrary, 
in the modern Theory of Matter, 
we retain ‘nows’ and ‘heres’ 
for the fundamental objects of reality. 

These primitives 
are no less important 
in the formulation 
of the subatomic laws 
of quantum theory 
than in general relativity. 

The new feature is that 
the fundamental objects of reality 
are one step removed 
from the directly observed: 
they are quantum fields, 
rather than physical events.

It is possible 
to avoid ordinary language
and its snares. 

Within specific domains of mathematics, 
this is accomplished by constructing
exact definitions and axioms. 

Purity of language is also forced on us 
when we interact with modern digital computers,
since they do not tolerate ambiguity.

But the purity of artificial languages 
comes at a great cost in scope, 
suppleness and flexibility.

Perhaps computers 
will become truly intelligent 
when they learn to be tolerant 
of ordinary, sloppy language 
— and then to use it themselves! 

In any case, for us humans 
the practical and wise course 
will be to continue 
to use ordinary language,
even for abstract scientific investigations, 
but to be very suspicious of it. 

Along these lines, 
Heisenberg’s considered formulation, 
put forward in The Physical Principles 
of Quantum Theory in 1930, was: 

“[I]t is found advisable to introduce
a great wealth of concepts 
into a physical theory, 
without attempting 
to justify them rigorously, 
and then to allow experiment to decide 
at what points a revision is necessary.”

Looking to the future, 
after ‘now’ and ‘here’,
what basic intuition 
will next require reformation?

As the nature of mind 
comes into scientific focus, 
might it be ‘I’? 

Perhaps the following remarks 
of Hermann Weyl, stimulated 
by deep reflection on the aspects 
of modern physics discussed here 
and stated in his Philosophy of Mathematics 
and Natural Science (1949), point in that direction: 

“The objective world 
simply is, it does not happen. 
Only to the gaze of my consciousness, 
crawling upward along the life line of my body, 
does a section of this world come to life 
as a fleeting image in space 
which continuously changes in time.” 

_________________________________________
Frank Wilczek is in the Massachusetts Institute of
Technology, Cambridge, Massachusetts 20139, USA.

No hay comentarios:

Publicar un comentario

COMENTE SIN RESTRICCIONES PERO ATÉNGASE A SUS CONSECUENCIAS